Main Page
From Logic
(86 intermediate revisions not shown) | |||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
- | + | This site is part of Candle In The Dark, a series of interconnected websites devoted to philosophy and science. See also: http://editthis.info/scientificmetho, http://editthis.info/atheology and http://www.edithis.info/criticalthought | |
- | + | This site is intended as a resource for those interested in learning Logic. While the author of this page will take a scholarly approach to the subject, this page will approach the subject in a more user-friendly manner than available at Wikipedia, at times even using colloquial language. The site will offer a full [[Course in Logic 101]], based on two of the most reliable texts on logic: Copi and Cohen's ''Introduction to Logic (11th Edition)'' and Hurely's ''A Concise Introduction to Logic (7th Edition)''. The [[Course in Logic 101|course]] will cover the basics of Logic, [[Classical Logic]], [[Propositional Logic]], [[Predicate Logic]], [[Modal Logic]] and [[Inductive Logic]] including a discussion of [[Inductive Logic|Bayesian Theory]]. Those interested in taking the [[Course in Logic 101|course]] can consult that page for the proper order of reading the pages of this site. | |
- | + | ||
- | + | ||
- | + | ||
- | + | ||
- | + | Now, let's begin. | |
- | + | ||
- | * | + | |
+ | ==Nature of logic== | ||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | '''Logic''', (from the Greek word λόγος (''logos''), originally meaning ''the word'', but also referring to ''speech'' or ''reason'') is the science of evaluating the reasoning within [[Argument|arguments]]. It refers to any a set of rules that tell us when an [[argument|argument's]] premises support their conclusion (Hofweber 2004). Logic arose from a concern with correctness of [[argument]]ation (See [[Aristotle]]). | ||
+ | |||
+ | Surprised? People usually come to hold, through their lack of any formal training in logic, that logic is far more than it really is. Therefore, a further understanding of just what logic is, can be enhanced by delineating it from what it is not: | ||
+ | |||
+ | *Logic is not the study of what, if anything, comprises the 'groundness of being for the universe' - That's metaphysics. | ||
+ | *Logic is not a set of laws that governs the universe - That's physics. | ||
+ | *Logic is not an immaterial "entity" that transcends reality - Such discussions belong to the realm of theology. | ||
+ | *Logic is not a method for 'studying the world' - That's science. | ||
+ | *Logic is not the method for assessing axioms - That's a matter of pure reason. | ||
+ | *Logic is not a way of evaluating 'truth' - That's philosophy. | ||
+ | *Logic is not a set of laws that governs human behavior - That's psychology. | ||
+ | *Logic is not even a study of how people reason - [[Non Logical Modes of Thought|Fortunately]] there is more to human reason than just logic. | ||
+ | |||
+ | ===Relation to other sciences=== | ||
+ | |||
+ | Closely related to logic is semantics, or the philosophy of language, which concerns the meaning of the words and sentences; [[epistemology|epistemology]], or the theory of knowledge, which concerns the conditions under which assertions are true; and the psychology of reasoning, which concerns the mental processes involved in reasoning. Logic, however, is generally understood to describe reasoning in a prescriptive manner (i.e. it describes how reasoning ought to take place), whereas psychology is descriptive and therefore more inclusive vis-a-vis the various methods of judgment humans actually use. | ||
+ | |||
+ | ===Definition of an Argument=== | ||
+ | |||
+ | An [[argument]] is made up of a group of statements we call [[proposition]]s. We use the term [[proposition]] instead of sentence because a proposition is more than just a sentence, it is a declarative sentence that contains a [[truth value]]. In the case of [[Classical Logic]], which is based on the [[Law of the Excluded Middle]], this truth value must either be "true" or false" . | ||
+ | |||
+ | There are two types of [[proposition]]s. The first, the [[Premises|Premise]], makes a commitment to truth, and is used as evidence to support the second type of proposition, the [[Conclusion]], which is the claim the arguer wants to prove. An argument must at least imply one of each. The study of logic, therefore, is the effort to determine the conditions under which one is justified in passing from the premises to the conclusion that logically must follow them. | ||
+ | |||
+ | === Examining Arguments: Informal, formal, and symbolic logic=== | ||
+ | |||
+ | Arguments can be examined through examining their premises, the form of the argument, and by looking at them abstractly. We use the terms "informal", "formal" and "symbolic" to capture these meanings. | ||
+ | |||
+ | * '''[[Formal and Informal Logic|Informal Logic]]''' is the study of natural language [[Argument|arguments]]. The study of fallacies is an especially important branch of informal logic. | ||
+ | |||
+ | * '''[[Formal and Informal Logic|Formal Logic]]''' is the study of inference with purely formal content, where that content is made explicit. (An inference possesses a purely formal content if it can be expressed as a particular application of a wholly abstract rule, that is, a rule that is not about any particular thing or property. We will see later that on many definitions of logic, logical inference and inference with purely formal content are the same thing. This does not render the notion of informal logic vacuous, since one may wish to investigate logic without committing to a ''particular'' formal analysis.) | ||
+ | * '''[[Propositional Logic|Symbolic Logic]]''' is closely related to formal logic: it the study of symbolic abstractions that capture the formal features of logical inference. | ||
+ | |||
+ | ===Consistency, soundness, and completeness=== | ||
+ | |||
+ | There are three valuable properties that formal systems can have: | ||
+ | |||
+ | :* '''[[Consistency]]''', which means that none of the theorems of the system contradict each other. | ||
+ | |||
+ | :* '''[[Validity, Strength, Soundness and Cogency|Soundness]]''', which means that the system's rules of derivation will never let you infer anything false, so long as you start with only true premises. So if a system is sound (and its axioms, if any, are true), then the theorems of a sound formal system are the [[truth]]s. All of the theorems of a system that has no axioms are its truths and sometimes the truths of such a system are called 'logical truths.' (Note that if a system is not consistent, it cannot be sound. This is because a contradiction is always false, so if two theorems contradict at least one is false.) | ||
+ | |||
+ | :* '''[[Completeness]]''', which means that there are no true sentences in the system that cannot, at least in principle, be proved using the derivation rules (and axioms, if any) of the system. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Good luck finding systems that achieve all three virtues. It has been proven by [[Kurt Godel]] that a system with enough axioms and/or rules of derivation to derive the principles of arithmetic cannot be both consistent and complete. This is called [[Godel's Incompleteness Theorem]]. | ||
+ | |||
+ | ===Deductive and inductive reasoning=== | ||
+ | |||
+ | Originally, logic consisted only of [[Deductive and Inductive Logic|deductive reasoning]] which concerns what follows universally from given premises. However, it is important to note that [[Deductive and Inductive Logic|inductive reasoning]]—the study of deriving a reliable generalization from observations—has sometimes been included in the study of logic. Correspondingly, we must distinguish between deductive validity and inductive validity. An inference is deductively valid if and only if there is no possible situation in which all the premises are true and the conclusion false. The notion of deductive validity can be rigorously stated for systems of [[Formal and Informal Logic|formal logic]] in terms of the well-understood notions of [[semantics]]. Inductive validity on the other hand requires us to define a ''reliable generalization'' of some set of observations. The task of providing this definition may be approached in various ways, some less formal than others; some of these definitions may use [[mathematical model]]s of probability. For the most part this discussion of logic deals only with deductive logic. | ||
+ | |||
+ | ==Types of logic== | ||
+ | |||
+ | Formal logic encompasses a wide variety of logical systems. Various systems of logic include [[Classical Logic|Classical]] or [[Classical Logic|Syllogistic logic]], [[Predicate Logic]], [[Propositional Logic]], and [[Modal Logic]], and formal systems are indispensable in all branches of [[mathematical logic]]. | ||
+ | |||
+ | ===Syllogistic or Classical Logic=== | ||
+ | |||
+ | The ''Organon'' was [[Aristotle]]'s body of work on logic, with the ''Prior Analytics'' constituting the first explicit work in [[Formal and Informal Logic|formal logic]], introducing to the world the [[Syllogism|syllogism]]. [[Classical Logic|Syllogistic Logic]], [[Classical Logic|Term logic]], [[Classical Logic|Aristotelean Logic]] or [[Classical Logic]] are all references to the logical form of the [[Syllogism|syllogism]]. Syllogistic logic is the analysis of the judgments into propositions consisting of two terms that are related by one of a fixed number of relations, and the expression of inferences by means of [[syllogism]]s that consisted of two propositions sharing a common term as premise, and a conclusion which was a proposition involving the two unrelated terms from the premises. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Aristotle's work was regarded in classical times and from medieval times in Europe and the Middle East as the very picture of a fully worked out system. It was not alone: the [[Stoics]] proposed a system of [[Propositional Logic]] that was studied by medieval logicians; nor was the perfection of Aristotle's system undisputed; for example the [[problem of multiple generality]] was recognized in medieval times. Nonetheless, problems with syllogistic logic were not seen as being in need of revolutionary solutions. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Today, some academics claim that Aristotle's system is generally seen as having little more than historical value (though there is some current interest in extending term logics), regarded as made obsolete by the advent of [[Sentential Logic]] and the [[Predicate Logic|predicate calculus]]. | ||
+ | |||
+ | ===Propositional Logic=== | ||
+ | |||
+ | Logic as it is studied today is a very different subject from [[Classical Logic]]; the principal difference is the innovation of [[Propositional Logic]] and [[Predicate Logic]]. Propositional Logic allows for more complex argument forms than classical syllogisms. In propositional logic, propositions are represented by ''symbols'' and ''connectors'', so that the statement's logical form can be assessed for cases of truth and falsity, which in turn allows us to assess the entire argument's form for validity or invalidity. In symbolic, or propositional logic, a simple statement, containing one proposition, is is referred to as an ''atomic statement'', and is symbolized by one letter, such as p. A compound statement, with more than one proposition holding some relationship to another proposition, is referred to as a molecular statement, which may be symbolized as p v q. The v symbol just used is a connective: Atomic propositions become molecular propositions when they are joined by connectives. | ||
+ | |||
+ | ===Predicate Logic=== | ||
+ | |||
+ | However, just as limits in Classical Logical led to [[Propositional Logic]], limits in Propositional Logic pointed to the need for a new logic. Propositional Logic is not adequate for formalizing valid arguments that rely on the internal structure of the propositions involved. For example, a translation of the valid argument: | ||
+ | |||
+ | * All men are mortal | ||
+ | * Socrates is a man | ||
+ | * Therefore, Socrates is mortal | ||
+ | |||
+ | into propositional logic yields | ||
+ | |||
+ | * A | ||
+ | * B | ||
+ | * ∴ C (∴ means "therefore" | ||
+ | |||
+ | which is invalid, because there are no connectors between the premises and between the premises and the conclusion. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Therefore, the need for a ''First Order'', or [[Predicate Logic]] became apparent. The new ingredient of first-order logic not found in propositional logic is [[Predicate Logic|quantification]]: where φ is any (well-formed) formula, the new constructions ∀x φ and ∃x φ — read "for all x, φ" and "for some x, φ" — are introduced, where x is an individual variable whose range is the set of individuals of some given universe of discourse (or domain). For example, if the universe consists solely of people, then x ranges over people. or convenience, we write φ as φ(x) to show that it contains only the variable x free and, for b a member of the universe, we let φ[b] express that b satisfies (i.e. has the property expressed by) φ. Then ∀x φ(x) states that φ[b] is true for every b in the universe, and ∃x φ(x) means that there is a b (in the universe) such that φ[b] holds. | ||
+ | |||
+ | The argument about Socrates can be formalized in first-order logic as follows. Let the universe of discourse be the set of all people, living and deceased, and let Man(x) be a predicate (which, informally, means that the person represented by variable x is a man) and Mortal(x) be a second predicate. Then the argument above becomes | ||
+ | |||
+ | * ∀ x (Man(x) → Mortal(x)) | ||
+ | * Man(Socrates) | ||
+ | * ∴ Mortal(Socrates) | ||
+ | |||
+ | A literal translation of the first line would be "For all x, if x is described by 'Man', x must also be described by 'Mortal'." The second line states that the predicate "Man" applies to Socrates, and the third line translates to "Therefore, the description 'Mortal' applies to Socrates." | ||
+ | |||
+ | ===Modal logic=== | ||
+ | |||
+ | http://www.thadguy.com/wp-content/uploads/2007/07/modal-logic-can-solve-all-problems.png | ||
+ | |||
+ | The concepts behind Modal Logic date back to [[Aristotle]], who was concerned with the [[alethic modalities]] of necessity and possibility, which he observed to be dual in the sense of [[De Morgan duality]]. While the study of necessity and possibility remained important to philosophers, little logical innovation happened until the landmark investigations of Clarence Irving Lewis in 1918, who formulated a family of rival axiomatisations of the alethic modalities. His work unleashed a torrent of new work on the topic, expanding the kinds of modality treated to include [[deontic logic]] and [[epistemic logic]]. The seminal work of [[Arthur Prior]] applied the same formal language to treat [[temporal logic]] and paved the way for the marriage of the two subjects. Saul Kripke discovered (contemporaneously with rivals) his theory of [[frame semantics]] which revolutionized the formal technology available to modal logicians and gave a new [[graph theory|graph-theoretic]] way of looking at modality that has driven many applications in [[computational linguistics]] and [[computer science]], such as [[dynamic logic]]. | ||
+ | |||
+ | ==Review== | ||
+ | |||
+ | If this all seems a blur at this point, never fear<BR> | ||
+ | |||
+ | http://i602.photobucket.com/albums/tt102/hanniballecturer/candleinthedark/drsmith_peaceful.jpg | ||
+ | |||
+ | Smith is here. | ||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | Every key point on this page will be explained, in detail, in the following sections. Students following the [[Course in Logic 101]] should proceed to the section entitled: [[The Laws of Classical Logic]] | ||
+ | |||
+ | ==References== | ||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | * Copi, I. M, Cohen, C., (2001), ''Introduction to Logic'', 11th Edition. | ||
+ | |||
+ | * Gabbay, D.M., and Guenthner, F. (eds., 2001-2005), ''Handbook of Philosophical Logic'', 13 vols., 2nd edition, Kluwer Publishers, Dordrecht. | ||
+ | |||
+ | * Hilbert, D., and Ackermann, W. (1928), ''Grundzüge der theoretischen Logik'' (''Principles of Theoretical Logic''), Springer-Verlag. | ||
+ | |||
+ | * Hodges, W. (2001), ''Logic. An introduction to Elementary Logic'', Penguin Books. | ||
+ | |||
+ | * Hofweber, T. (2004), "Logic and Ontology", ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', Edward N. Zalta (ed.), [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-ontology/ Eprint]. | ||
+ | |||
+ | * Hughes, R.I.G. (ed., 1993), ''A Philosophical Companion to First-Order Logic'', Hackett Publishing. | ||
+ | |||
+ | * Hurely, P. J. (2000) ''A Concise Introduction to Logic'' - 7th Edition | ||
+ | |||
+ | * Kneale, W., and Kneale, M., (1962), ''The Development of Logic'', Oxford University Press, London, UK. | ||
+ | |||
+ | * Priest, G. (2004), "Dialetheism", ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', Edward N. Zalta (ed.), [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/dialetheism Eprint]. | ||
+ | |||
+ | ==See also== | ||
+ | * [[Course in Logic 101]] This takes the interested reader to every major page of the site. | ||
+ | * [[The Laws of Classical Logic]] This page presents the axioms of classical logic | ||
+ | * [[Validity, Strength, Soundness and Cogency ]] | ||
+ | * [[Deductive and Inductive Logic]] | ||
+ | * [[Fallacies|Logical Fallacies]] | ||
+ | * [[Informal Fallacies]] This page presents a list of informal fallacies found in arguments. | ||
+ | * [[Formal Fallacies]] This page examines both valid and invalid logical forms. | ||
+ | * [[Categorical Propositions]] | ||
+ | * [[Classical Logic]] | ||
+ | * [[Propositional Logic]] | ||
+ | * [[Predicate Logic]] | ||
+ | * [[Inductive Logic]] | ||
+ | * [[Metalogic]] | ||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | [[Category:Logic]] | ||
+ | [[Category:Tutorials]] |
Current revision as of 14:13, 20 March 2015
This site is part of Candle In The Dark, a series of interconnected websites devoted to philosophy and science. See also: http://editthis.info/scientificmetho, http://editthis.info/atheology and http://www.edithis.info/criticalthought
This site is intended as a resource for those interested in learning Logic. While the author of this page will take a scholarly approach to the subject, this page will approach the subject in a more user-friendly manner than available at Wikipedia, at times even using colloquial language. The site will offer a full Course in Logic 101, based on two of the most reliable texts on logic: Copi and Cohen's Introduction to Logic (11th Edition) and Hurely's A Concise Introduction to Logic (7th Edition). The course will cover the basics of Logic, Classical Logic, Propositional Logic, Predicate Logic, Modal Logic and Inductive Logic including a discussion of Bayesian Theory. Those interested in taking the course can consult that page for the proper order of reading the pages of this site.
Now, let's begin.
Contents |
Nature of logic
Logic, (from the Greek word λόγος (logos), originally meaning the word, but also referring to speech or reason) is the science of evaluating the reasoning within arguments. It refers to any a set of rules that tell us when an argument's premises support their conclusion (Hofweber 2004). Logic arose from a concern with correctness of argumentation (See Aristotle).
Surprised? People usually come to hold, through their lack of any formal training in logic, that logic is far more than it really is. Therefore, a further understanding of just what logic is, can be enhanced by delineating it from what it is not:
- Logic is not the study of what, if anything, comprises the 'groundness of being for the universe' - That's metaphysics.
- Logic is not a set of laws that governs the universe - That's physics.
- Logic is not an immaterial "entity" that transcends reality - Such discussions belong to the realm of theology.
- Logic is not a method for 'studying the world' - That's science.
- Logic is not the method for assessing axioms - That's a matter of pure reason.
- Logic is not a way of evaluating 'truth' - That's philosophy.
- Logic is not a set of laws that governs human behavior - That's psychology.
- Logic is not even a study of how people reason - Fortunately there is more to human reason than just logic.
Relation to other sciences
Closely related to logic is semantics, or the philosophy of language, which concerns the meaning of the words and sentences; epistemology, or the theory of knowledge, which concerns the conditions under which assertions are true; and the psychology of reasoning, which concerns the mental processes involved in reasoning. Logic, however, is generally understood to describe reasoning in a prescriptive manner (i.e. it describes how reasoning ought to take place), whereas psychology is descriptive and therefore more inclusive vis-a-vis the various methods of judgment humans actually use.
Definition of an Argument
An argument is made up of a group of statements we call propositions. We use the term proposition instead of sentence because a proposition is more than just a sentence, it is a declarative sentence that contains a truth value. In the case of Classical Logic, which is based on the Law of the Excluded Middle, this truth value must either be "true" or false" .
There are two types of propositions. The first, the Premise, makes a commitment to truth, and is used as evidence to support the second type of proposition, the Conclusion, which is the claim the arguer wants to prove. An argument must at least imply one of each. The study of logic, therefore, is the effort to determine the conditions under which one is justified in passing from the premises to the conclusion that logically must follow them.
Examining Arguments: Informal, formal, and symbolic logic
Arguments can be examined through examining their premises, the form of the argument, and by looking at them abstractly. We use the terms "informal", "formal" and "symbolic" to capture these meanings.
- Informal Logic is the study of natural language arguments. The study of fallacies is an especially important branch of informal logic.
- Formal Logic is the study of inference with purely formal content, where that content is made explicit. (An inference possesses a purely formal content if it can be expressed as a particular application of a wholly abstract rule, that is, a rule that is not about any particular thing or property. We will see later that on many definitions of logic, logical inference and inference with purely formal content are the same thing. This does not render the notion of informal logic vacuous, since one may wish to investigate logic without committing to a particular formal analysis.)
- Symbolic Logic is closely related to formal logic: it the study of symbolic abstractions that capture the formal features of logical inference.
Consistency, soundness, and completeness
There are three valuable properties that formal systems can have:
- Consistency, which means that none of the theorems of the system contradict each other.
- Soundness, which means that the system's rules of derivation will never let you infer anything false, so long as you start with only true premises. So if a system is sound (and its axioms, if any, are true), then the theorems of a sound formal system are the truths. All of the theorems of a system that has no axioms are its truths and sometimes the truths of such a system are called 'logical truths.' (Note that if a system is not consistent, it cannot be sound. This is because a contradiction is always false, so if two theorems contradict at least one is false.)
- Completeness, which means that there are no true sentences in the system that cannot, at least in principle, be proved using the derivation rules (and axioms, if any) of the system.
Good luck finding systems that achieve all three virtues. It has been proven by Kurt Godel that a system with enough axioms and/or rules of derivation to derive the principles of arithmetic cannot be both consistent and complete. This is called Godel's Incompleteness Theorem.
Deductive and inductive reasoning
Originally, logic consisted only of deductive reasoning which concerns what follows universally from given premises. However, it is important to note that inductive reasoning—the study of deriving a reliable generalization from observations—has sometimes been included in the study of logic. Correspondingly, we must distinguish between deductive validity and inductive validity. An inference is deductively valid if and only if there is no possible situation in which all the premises are true and the conclusion false. The notion of deductive validity can be rigorously stated for systems of formal logic in terms of the well-understood notions of semantics. Inductive validity on the other hand requires us to define a reliable generalization of some set of observations. The task of providing this definition may be approached in various ways, some less formal than others; some of these definitions may use mathematical models of probability. For the most part this discussion of logic deals only with deductive logic.
Types of logic
Formal logic encompasses a wide variety of logical systems. Various systems of logic include Classical or Syllogistic logic, Predicate Logic, Propositional Logic, and Modal Logic, and formal systems are indispensable in all branches of mathematical logic.
Syllogistic or Classical Logic
The Organon was Aristotle's body of work on logic, with the Prior Analytics constituting the first explicit work in formal logic, introducing to the world the syllogism. Syllogistic Logic, Term logic, Aristotelean Logic or Classical Logic are all references to the logical form of the syllogism. Syllogistic logic is the analysis of the judgments into propositions consisting of two terms that are related by one of a fixed number of relations, and the expression of inferences by means of syllogisms that consisted of two propositions sharing a common term as premise, and a conclusion which was a proposition involving the two unrelated terms from the premises.
Aristotle's work was regarded in classical times and from medieval times in Europe and the Middle East as the very picture of a fully worked out system. It was not alone: the Stoics proposed a system of Propositional Logic that was studied by medieval logicians; nor was the perfection of Aristotle's system undisputed; for example the problem of multiple generality was recognized in medieval times. Nonetheless, problems with syllogistic logic were not seen as being in need of revolutionary solutions.
Today, some academics claim that Aristotle's system is generally seen as having little more than historical value (though there is some current interest in extending term logics), regarded as made obsolete by the advent of Sentential Logic and the predicate calculus.
Propositional Logic
Logic as it is studied today is a very different subject from Classical Logic; the principal difference is the innovation of Propositional Logic and Predicate Logic. Propositional Logic allows for more complex argument forms than classical syllogisms. In propositional logic, propositions are represented by symbols and connectors, so that the statement's logical form can be assessed for cases of truth and falsity, which in turn allows us to assess the entire argument's form for validity or invalidity. In symbolic, or propositional logic, a simple statement, containing one proposition, is is referred to as an atomic statement, and is symbolized by one letter, such as p. A compound statement, with more than one proposition holding some relationship to another proposition, is referred to as a molecular statement, which may be symbolized as p v q. The v symbol just used is a connective: Atomic propositions become molecular propositions when they are joined by connectives.
Predicate Logic
However, just as limits in Classical Logical led to Propositional Logic, limits in Propositional Logic pointed to the need for a new logic. Propositional Logic is not adequate for formalizing valid arguments that rely on the internal structure of the propositions involved. For example, a translation of the valid argument:
* All men are mortal * Socrates is a man * Therefore, Socrates is mortal
into propositional logic yields
* A * B * ∴ C (∴ means "therefore"
which is invalid, because there are no connectors between the premises and between the premises and the conclusion.
Therefore, the need for a First Order, or Predicate Logic became apparent. The new ingredient of first-order logic not found in propositional logic is quantification: where φ is any (well-formed) formula, the new constructions ∀x φ and ∃x φ — read "for all x, φ" and "for some x, φ" — are introduced, where x is an individual variable whose range is the set of individuals of some given universe of discourse (or domain). For example, if the universe consists solely of people, then x ranges over people. or convenience, we write φ as φ(x) to show that it contains only the variable x free and, for b a member of the universe, we let φ[b] express that b satisfies (i.e. has the property expressed by) φ. Then ∀x φ(x) states that φ[b] is true for every b in the universe, and ∃x φ(x) means that there is a b (in the universe) such that φ[b] holds.
The argument about Socrates can be formalized in first-order logic as follows. Let the universe of discourse be the set of all people, living and deceased, and let Man(x) be a predicate (which, informally, means that the person represented by variable x is a man) and Mortal(x) be a second predicate. Then the argument above becomes
* ∀ x (Man(x) → Mortal(x)) * Man(Socrates) * ∴ Mortal(Socrates)
A literal translation of the first line would be "For all x, if x is described by 'Man', x must also be described by 'Mortal'." The second line states that the predicate "Man" applies to Socrates, and the third line translates to "Therefore, the description 'Mortal' applies to Socrates."
Modal logic
The concepts behind Modal Logic date back to Aristotle, who was concerned with the alethic modalities of necessity and possibility, which he observed to be dual in the sense of De Morgan duality. While the study of necessity and possibility remained important to philosophers, little logical innovation happened until the landmark investigations of Clarence Irving Lewis in 1918, who formulated a family of rival axiomatisations of the alethic modalities. His work unleashed a torrent of new work on the topic, expanding the kinds of modality treated to include deontic logic and epistemic logic. The seminal work of Arthur Prior applied the same formal language to treat temporal logic and paved the way for the marriage of the two subjects. Saul Kripke discovered (contemporaneously with rivals) his theory of frame semantics which revolutionized the formal technology available to modal logicians and gave a new graph-theoretic way of looking at modality that has driven many applications in computational linguistics and computer science, such as dynamic logic.
Review
If this all seems a blur at this point, never fear
Smith is here.
Every key point on this page will be explained, in detail, in the following sections. Students following the Course in Logic 101 should proceed to the section entitled: The Laws of Classical Logic
References
- Copi, I. M, Cohen, C., (2001), Introduction to Logic, 11th Edition.
- Gabbay, D.M., and Guenthner, F. (eds., 2001-2005), Handbook of Philosophical Logic, 13 vols., 2nd edition, Kluwer Publishers, Dordrecht.
- Hilbert, D., and Ackermann, W. (1928), Grundzüge der theoretischen Logik (Principles of Theoretical Logic), Springer-Verlag.
- Hodges, W. (2001), Logic. An introduction to Elementary Logic, Penguin Books.
- Hofweber, T. (2004), "Logic and Ontology", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Edward N. Zalta (ed.), Eprint.
- Hughes, R.I.G. (ed., 1993), A Philosophical Companion to First-Order Logic, Hackett Publishing.
- Hurely, P. J. (2000) A Concise Introduction to Logic - 7th Edition
- Kneale, W., and Kneale, M., (1962), The Development of Logic, Oxford University Press, London, UK.
- Priest, G. (2004), "Dialetheism", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Edward N. Zalta (ed.), Eprint.
See also
- Course in Logic 101 This takes the interested reader to every major page of the site.
- The Laws of Classical Logic This page presents the axioms of classical logic
- Validity, Strength, Soundness and Cogency
- Deductive and Inductive Logic
- Logical Fallacies
- Informal Fallacies This page presents a list of informal fallacies found in arguments.
- Formal Fallacies This page examines both valid and invalid logical forms.
- Categorical Propositions
- Classical Logic
- Propositional Logic
- Predicate Logic
- Inductive Logic
- Metalogic