Deductive and Inductive Logic
From Logic
m (→Deductive Logic) |
m (→References) |
||
Line 59: | Line 59: | ||
* Hurely, P. J. (2000) A Concise Introduction to Logic - 7th Edition | * Hurely, P. J. (2000) A Concise Introduction to Logic - 7th Edition | ||
+ | * Pierce, C. S. (1903) P Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce (Volumes I-VI, ed. by Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiß, Volumes VII-VIII, ed. by Arthur W. Burks). Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard UP. |
Revision as of 20:49, 29 July 2007
What is deduction? What is induction? How do they differ?
Contents |
Deductive Logic
Deductive Logic is the method of non contradictory identification. It is based on the classical axioms of Aristotelean logic. Deductive arguments are akin to mathematical equations: they present a series of categories or definitions in a series of equivalencies. For this reason, the conclusion of a deductive argument necessarily follows from its premises, in the same way that 4 follows from the "premises" of 2+2=. In the opinion of this author, the most elegant form of a deductive argument is Aristotle's syllogistic logic, or classical deductive logic.
Generally, it is held by logicians that deductive arguments work from general rules to specific conclusions. For example, consider this categorical syllogism:
All humans are mortal Socrates is human Therefore, Socrates is mortal
This syllogism works from a general rule: "all humans are mortal" to a specific conclusion: "Socrates is mortal". However, it is not necessary that deductive arguments move from general or universal statements, to specific or particular statements, for example, a deductive argument can work from particular premises, consider this disjunctive syllogism:
If Socrates if human, then Socrates is mortal Socrates is human Therefore, Socrates is mortal
We can call a deductive logical system an a priori system. This means that we can make up such a system without any observation or experimental examination.We can create a set of categories like squares or circles or letters, and a set of self consitent rules that follow a set of definitions, all without having to ever experience such "things".
Philosophers like to say that a "brain in vat" set apart from the rest of the universe could create an a priori system.
Inductive Logic
Inductive arguments are not like mathematical equations at all, they are akin to predictions - i.e. they are probable claims. They don't work with abstract entities like categories or definitions, they work with empirical claims from the physical world outside of our imaginations. The "real world" outside of our imaginations does not give us a set of abstract categories, it gives us a set of imprecise entities that exist along an imprecise continuum. For this reason, inductive arguments do not posses the certainty of deductive arguments. All inductive arguments are uncertain and open to questioning.
"Don't speak to me in absolutes, the evidence IS contestable!"
(Dr Zaius to Cornelius, regarding archeological (inductive) evidence, in Planet of the Apes - one of the few instances where Hollywood's take on science was right on the money.)
When dealing with inductive arguments, we can only say that the conclusion is likely to follow from the premises.
Some logicians hold that induction works from "particulars to general rules of inference"
I have seen many crows All of them were black It stands to reason that all crows are probably black
But again, inductive arguments can work from general rules to particular conclusions, or from particular premises to particular conclusions
Examples of inductive arguments would include arguments from analogy (which are always imperfect), generalizations from a sample to a group,), and, from causal inferences (from cause to effect OR from effect to cause or arguments based on signs or evidence. If you are a fan of the famous sleuth Sherlock Holmes, who often worked from signs and evidence, you will quickly realize from this definition that Holmes was a famous INductiontionist, not, as he himself often claimed, a great deductionist!
Abduction
As a side note for later study (section to be added later), the logician Charles S. Peirce holds that we should also consider "abduction", which is defined as follows: "Abduction is the process of forming an explanatory hypothesis. It is the only logical operation which introduces any new idea" (Peirce, 1903:CP 5.171).
Review: Categories vs A Continuum
It was the great thinker Galileo who recognized the limitations of Aristotle's categorical paradigm - we can create abstract categories like squares, and set up deductive arguments that speak about equivalenceis between such categories, but categories have no real world correlate - we live in a changing world of impreciseness, where everything falls somewhere along a continuum. This is not to say that deduction has no use, after all, geometry also deals with categories like circles and squares, and is quite useful. It is only to say that while deductive arguments give us 'certain' conclusions, we cannot apply these certain conclusions to the real world without error.
Those following the Course in Logic 101 should proceed to the next section: Validity, Strength, Soundness and Cogency
References
- Hurely, P. J. (2000) A Concise Introduction to Logic - 7th Edition
- Pierce, C. S. (1903) P Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce (Volumes I-VI, ed. by Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiß, Volumes VII-VIII, ed. by Arthur W. Burks). Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard UP.