Main Page

From Logic

(Difference between revisions)
Line 1: Line 1:
 +
==Introduction==
-
"It's not whether you feel you are right - it whether you have a good reason to think you are right."
+
This site is intended as a resource for those interested in learning Logic. While the author of this page will take a scholarly approach to the subject, this page will approach the subject in a more user friendly manner than available at Wikipedia, at times even using colloquial language. The site will offer a full [[Course in Logic 101]], based on two of the most reliable texts on logic: Copi and Cohen's ''Introduction to Logic (11th Edition)'' and Hurely's ''A Concise Introduction to Logic (7th Edition)''. The [[Course in Logic 101|course]] will cover the basics of Logic, [[Classical Logic]], [[Propositional Logic]], [[Predicate Logic]], [[Modal Logic]] and [[Inductive Logic]] including a discussion of [[Inductive Logic|Bayesian Theory]]. Those interested in taking the [[Course in Logic 101|course]] can consult that page for the proper order of reading the pages of this site.
 +
Now, let's begin.
-
Everyone has an opinion, and in a democratic country everyone also has an equal right to state it, but not everyone's opinion is of equal value. The opinion of Einstein on physics is superior to that of Captain Kangaroo's. The opinion of Harry Truman on democracy is superior to that of Bozo the Clown's. And the reason for this is not solely because Einstein and Truman are well known "authorities", the reason is that each of these experts has a reasoned grounds for holding to their views based on experience, factual knowledge, evidence and a rational argument based on these facts.
+
'''Logic''', (from the Greek word λόγος (''logos''), originally meaning ''the word'', but also referring to ''speech'' or ''reason'') is the science of evaluating the reasoning within [[Argument|arguments]].
-
This page exists to spread this truth - some opinions ARE worth more than others. And if you want yours to be one of the more valid, convincing, and simply BETTER opinions, you must learn how to argue your points using the tenets of LOGIC.
+
==Nature of logic== 
-
Let's begin  
+
Logic arose from a concern with correctness of [[argument]]ation (See [[Aristotle]]).  Logic is generally accepted and understood by logicians as a set of rules that tell us when an [[argument|argument's]] premises support their conclusion. Logic specifically deals with inferences whose validity can be traced back to the formal features of the representations that are involved in that inference.'' (Hofweber 2004).  
-
'''Logic''', from Classical Greek λόγος ([[logos]]), originally meaning ''the word'', or ''what is spoken'', (but coming to mean ''thought'' or ''reason'') is most often said to be the study of criteria for the evaluation of [[logical argument|arguments]], although the exact definition of logic is a matter of controversy among philosophers. However the subject is grounded, the task of the logician is the same: to advance an account of valid and fallacious [[inference]] to allow one to distinguish logical from flawed arguments.
+
Therefore, a further understanding of just what logic is, can be enhanced by delineating it from what it is not:
-
Traditionally, logic is studied as a branch of [[philosophy]].  Since the mid-nineteenth century logic has been commonly studied in [[mathematics]] and [[law]]. More recently logic is applied in [[computer science]] and [[artificial intelligence]]As a [[formal science]], logic investigates and classifies the structure of statements and arguments, both through the study of [[formal system]]s of [[inference]] and through the study of arguments in natural language. The scope of logic can therefore be very large, ranging from core topics such as the study of [[fallacies]] and [[paradox]]es, to specialist analyses of reasoning such as [[probability|probably]] correct reasoning and arguments involving [[causality]].  Logic is also commonly used today in [[argumentation theory]].  
+
*Logic is not the 'groundness of being' - that's metaphysics.
 +
*Logic is not a set of laws that governs the universe - that's physics.  
 +
*Logic is not an immaterial "entity" that transcends reality - that's speculative theology.
 +
*Logic is no a method for 'studying the world' - that's science.
 +
*Logic is not the method for assessing axioms - that's a matter of pure reason.
 +
*Logic is not a way of evaluating 'truth' - that's philosophy.
 +
*Logic is not a set of laws that governs human behavior - that's psychology.  
 +
*Logic is not even a study of how people reason - [[fortunately|Fortunately]] there is more to human reason than just logic.
-
==Nature of logic==
+
[[Immanuel Kant]] introduced an alternative idea as to what logic is.  He argued that logic should be conceived as the science of judgment, an idea taken up by [[Gottlob Frege]]. However, modern psychologists have demonstrated that a significant percentage of human judgment is clearly non logical.
-
The nature of logic has been the object of intense dispute: it is not possible to clearly delineate the bounds of logic in terms acceptable to all rival viewpoints.  Despite that controversy, the study of logic has been very coherent and technically grounded.  In this article, we first characterize logic by introducing fundamental ideas about form, then by outlining some schools of thought, as well as by giving a brief overview of logic's history, an account of its relationship to other sciences, and finally, an exposition of some of logic's essential concepts.
 
-
===Informal, formal, and symbolic logic===
+
===Relation to other sciences===
 +
 
 +
Closely related to logic is semantics, or the philosophy of language, which concerns the meaning of the words and sentences; epistemology, or the theory of knowledge, which concerns the conditions under which assertions are true; and the psychology of reasoning, which concerns the mental processes involved in reasoning.  Logic, however, is generally understood to describe reasoning in a prescriptive manner (i.e.  it describes how reasoning ought to take place), whereas psychology is descriptive and therefore more inclusive vis-a-vis the various methods of judgment humans actually use. 
-
The crucial concept of form is central to discussions of the nature of logic, and it complicates exposition that 'formal' in "formal logic" is commonly used in an ambiguous manner.  We shall start by giving definitions that we shall adhere to in the rest of this article:
+
===Definition of an Argument===
-
* '''[[Informal logic]]''' is the study of natural language [[Logical argument|arguments]].  The study of [[fallacies]] is an especially important branch of informal logic.
+
-
* '''Formal logic''' is the study of [[inference]] with purely formal content, where that content is made explicit. (An inference possesses a '''purely formal content''' if it can be expressed as a particular application of a wholly abstract rule, that is, a rule that is not about any particular thing or property.  We will see later that on many definitions of logic, logical inference and inference with purely formal content are the same thing.  This does not render the notion of informal logic vacuous, since one may wish to investigate logic without committing to a ''particular'' formal analysis.)
+
-
* '''[[Symbolic logic]]''' is the study of symbolic abstractions that capture the formal features of logical inference.
+
-
The ambiguity is that "formal logic" is very often used with the alternate meaning of symbolic logic as we have defined it, with informal logic meaning any logical investigation that does not involve symbolic abstraction; it is this sense of 'formal' that is parallel to the received usages coming from "[[formal language]]s" or "[[formal theory]]".
+
An [[argument]] is made up of a group  of statements we call [[propositions]]. We use the term [[proposition]] instead of [[sentence]] because a proposition is more than just a sentence, it is a declarative sentence that contains a [[truth value]]. In the case of [[Classical Logic]], which is based on the [[Law of the Excluded Middle]], this truth value must  either be "true" or false" .  
-
While formal logic is old, dating back more than two millennia, most of symbolic logic is comparatively new, and arises with the application of insights from mathematics to problems in logic. Generally, a symbolic logic is captured by a [[formal system]], comprising a [[formal language]] including rules for creating expressions in the language, and a set of rules of derivation. The expressions will normally be intended to represent claims that we may be interested in, and likewise the rules of derivation represent inferences; such systems usually have an ''intended interpretation''.  
+
There are two types of [[Propositions]]. The first, the [[Premises|Premise]], makes a commitment to truth, and is used as evidence to support the second type of proposition, the [[Conclusion]], which is the claim the arguer wants to prove. An argument must at least imply one of each. The study of logic, therefore, is the effort to determine the conditions under which one is justified in passing from the premises to the conclusion that logically must follow them.  
-
For example, consider a very simple formal system that has just the symbols "p", "q", and "and" in its language. Its only rules for creating expressions are (1) "'p and q' and 'q and p' are expressions" and (2) Any expression compounded with another by 'and" is also an expression". Its only rule of derivation is "from any expression of the form 'p and q', you may conclude 'p'". The intended interpretation of the "p" and "q" is that they stand for any sentence. The intended interpretation of 'and' is expressed by specifying when sentences that contain 'and' are true. Most systems would interpret 'and' like this: sentences containing 'and' are true only when the expressions on either side of it (both of them) are true.
+
=== Examining Arguments: Informal, formal, and symbolic logic===
-
A formal system can also have [[axiom]]s. An axiom is a sentence that counts as always true within the system. For example, many systems have as an axiom the sentence "If P implies Q and P is the case, then Q is the case." To go along with the axioms the system will have a special rule of derivation, called the 'rule of substitution'. It says that you can derive from any axiom a sentence that is just like it, except that other sentences have been substituted for the 'P' and the 'Q'. For example, from the axiom above, we can conclude the following:  "If R&S implies that T or U, and R&S is the case; then it is the case that T or U." (This assumes that "R&S" and "T or U" are expressions in the formal system.) Most formal systems have either a rich set of rules of derivation, but few or no axioms; or a rich set of axioms but only the derivation rule of substitution.
+
Arguments can be examined through examining their premises, the form of the argument, and by looking at them abstractly. We use the terms "informal", "formal" and "symbolic" to capture these meanings.
-
Sentences that are derived using the system's axioms and rules of derivation are called [[theorems]].  
+
* '''[[Formal and Informal Logic|Informal Logic]]''' is the study of natural language [[Argument|arguments]].  The study of [[fallacies]] is an especially important branch of informal logic.
 +
* '''[[Formal and Informal Logic|Formal Logic]]''' is the study of [[inference]] with purely formal content, where that content is made explicit. (An inference possesses a purely formal content if it can be expressed as a particular application of a wholly abstract rule, that is, a rule that is not about any particular thing or property.  We will see later that on many definitions of logic, logical inference and inference with purely formal content are the same thing.  This does not render the notion of informal logic vacuous, since one may wish to investigate logic without committing to a ''particular'' formal analysis.)
 +
* '''[[Propositional Logic|Symbolic Logic]]''' is closely related to formal logic: it the study of symbolic abstractions that capture the formal features of logical inference.  
 +
 
 +
===Consistency, soundness, and completeness===
-
====Consistency, soundness,  and completeness====
 
There are three valuable properties that formal systems can have:
There are three valuable properties that formal systems can have:
:* '''[[Consistency]]''', which means that none of the theorems of the system contradict each other.
:* '''[[Consistency]]''', which means that none of the theorems of the system contradict each other.
-
:* '''[[soundness|Soundness]]''', which means that the system's rules of derivation will never let you infer anything false, so long as you start with only true premises.  So if a system is sound (and its axioms, if any, are true), then the theorems of a sound formal system are the [[truth]]s.  All of the theorems of a system that has no axioms are its truths and sometimes the truths of such a system are called 'logical truths.' (Note that if a system is not consistent, it cannot be sound. This is because a contradiction is always false, so if two theorems contradict at least one is false.)
+
:* '''[[Validity, Strength, Soundness and Cogency|Soundness]]''', which means that the system's rules of derivation will never let you infer anything false, so long as you start with only true premises.  So if a system is sound (and its axioms, if any, are true), then the theorems of a sound formal system are the [[truth]]s.  All of the theorems of a system that has no axioms are its truths and sometimes the truths of such a system are called 'logical truths.' (Note that if a system is not consistent, it cannot be sound. This is because a contradiction is always false, so if two theorems contradict at least one is false.)
:* '''[[Completeness]]''', which means that there are no true sentences in the system that cannot, at least in principle, be proved using the derivation rules (and axioms, if any) of the system.  
:* '''[[Completeness]]''', which means that there are no true sentences in the system that cannot, at least in principle, be proved using the derivation rules (and axioms, if any) of the system.  
Line 45: Line 55:
Not all systems achieve all three virtues. It has been proven by [[Kurt Gödel]] that a system with enough axioms and/or rules of derivation to derive the principles of arithmetic cannot be both consistent and complete. This is called [[Gödel's Incompleteness Theorem]].
Not all systems achieve all three virtues. It has been proven by [[Kurt Gödel]] that a system with enough axioms and/or rules of derivation to derive the principles of arithmetic cannot be both consistent and complete. This is called [[Gödel's Incompleteness Theorem]].
-
===Important families of formal systems===
+
===Deductive and inductive reasoning===
-
Formal logic encompasses a wide variety of logical systems.  Various systems of logic discussed below include [[term logic]], [[predicate logic]], [[propositional logic]], and [[modal logic]], and formal systems are indispensable in all branches of [[mathematical logic]].  The [[table of logic symbols]] describes various widely used notations in symbolic logic.
+
-
===Rival conceptions of logic===
+
Originally, logic consisted only of [[Deductive and Inductive Logic|deductive reasoning]] which concerns what follows universally from given premises.  However, it is important to note that [[Deductive and Inductive Logic|inductive reasoning]]—the study of deriving a reliable generalization from observations—has sometimes been included in the study of logic. Correspondingly, we must distinguish between deductive validity and inductive validity.  An inference is deductively valid if and only if there is no possible situation in which all the premises are true and the conclusion false.  The notion of deductive validity can be rigorously stated for systems of [[formal logic]] in terms of the well-understood notions of [[semantics]].  Inductive validity on the other hand requires us to define a ''reliable generalization'' of some set of observations. The task of providing this definition may be approached  in various ways, some less formal than others; some of these definitions may use [[mathematical model]]s of probability.  For the most part this discussion of logic deals only with deductive logic.
-
Logic arose (see below) from a concern with correctness of [[argumentation]]. The conception of logic as the study of argument is historically fundamental, and was how the founders of distinct traditions of logic, namely [[Plato]], [[Aristotle]], [[Mozi]] and [[Aksapada Gautama]], conceived of logic.  Modern logicians usually wish to ensure that logic studies just those arguments that arise from appropriately general forms of inference; so for example the [[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]] says of logic that it ''does not, however, cover good reasoning as a whole. That is the job of the theory of rationality. Rather it deals with inferences whose validity can be traced back to the formal features of the representations that are involved in that inference, be they linguistic, mental, or other representations'' (Hofweber 2004).
+
==Types of logic==
-
By contrast [[Immanuel Kant]] introduced an alternative idea as to what logic is.  He argued that logic should be conceived as the science of judgement, an idea taken up in [[Gottlob Frege]]'s logical and philosophical work, where thought (German: ''Gedanke'') is substituted for judgement (German: ''Urteil'')On this conception, the valid inferences of logic follow from the structural features of judgements or thoughts.
+
Formal logic encompasses a wide variety of logical systems.  Various systems of logic include [[Classical Logic|Classical]] or [[Classical Logic|Syllogistic logic]], [[Predicate Logic]], [[Propositional Logic]], and [[Modal Logic]], and formal systems are indispensable in all branches of [[mathematical logic]]The [[table of logic symbols]] describes various widely used notations in symbolic logic.
-
A third view of logic arises from the idea that logic is more fundamental than reason, and so that logic is the science of states of affairs (German: ''Sachverhalt'') in general.  [[Barry Smith]] locates  [[Franz Brentano]] as the source for this idea, an idea he claims reaches its fullest development in the work of [[Adolf Reinach]] (Smith 1989).  This view of logic appears radically distinct from the first: on this conception logic has no essential connection with argument, and the study of fallacies and paradoxes no longer appears essential to the discipline.
+
===Syllogistic or Classical Logic===
-
Occasionally one encounters a fourth view as to what logic is about: it is a purely formal manipulation of symbols according to some prescribed rules. This conception can be criticized on the grounds that the manipulation of just any formal system is usually not regarded as logic. Such accounts normally omit an explanation of what it is about certain formal systems that makes them systems of logic.
+
The ''Organon'' was [[Aristotle]]'s body of work on logic, with the ''[[Prior Analytics]]'' constituting the first explicit work in [[Informal logic|formal logic]], introducing to the world the [[Syllogism|syllogism]]. [[Classical Logic|Syllogistic Logic]], [[Classical Logic|Term logic]], [[Classical Logic|Aristotelean Logic]] or [[Classical Logic]] are all references to the logical form of the [[Syllogism|syllogism]]. Syllogistic logic is the analysis of the judgments into propositions consisting of two terms that are related by one of a fixed number of relations, and the expression of inferences by means of [[syllogism]]s that consisted of two propositions sharing a common term as premise, and a conclusion which was a proposition involving the two unrelated terms from the premises.
-
===Relation to other sciences===
+
Aristotle's work was regarded in classical times and from medieval times in Europe and the Middle East as the very picture of a fully worked out system.  It was not alone: the [[Stoics]] proposed a system of [[Propositional Logic]] that was studied by medieval logicians; nor was the perfection of Aristotle's system undisputed; for example the [[problem of multiple generality]] was recognized in medieval times.  Nonetheless, problems with syllogistic logic were not seen as being in need of revolutionary solutions.
-
Logic is related to rationality and the structure of concepts, and so has a degree of overlap with [[psychology]].  Logic is generally understood to describe reasoning in a prescriptive manner (i.e.  it describes how reasoning ought to take place), whereas psychology is descriptive, so the overlap is not so marked.  [[Gottlob Frege]], however, was adamant about [[anti-psychologism]]: that logic should be understood in a manner independent of the idiosyncrasies of how particular people might reason.
+
Today, some academics claim that Aristotle's system is generally seen as having little more than historical value (though there is some current interest in extending term logics), regarded as made obsolete by the advent of [[Sentential Logic]] and the [[Predicate Logic|predicate calculus]].
-
===Deductive and inductive reasoning===
+
===Propositional Logic===
 +
 +
Logic as it is studied today is a very different subject from [[Classical Logic]];  the principal difference is the innovation of [[Propositional Logic]] and [[Predicate Logic]]. Propositional Logic allows for more complex argument forms than classical syllogisms. In propositional logic, propositions are represented by ''symbols'' and ''connectors'', so that the statement's logical form can be assessed for cases of truth and falsity, which in turn allows us to assess the entire argument's form for validity or invalidity. In symbolic, or propositional logic, a simple statement, containing one proposition, is is referred to as an ''atomic statement'', and is symbolized by one letter, such as p. A compound statement, with more than one proposition holding some relationship to another proposition, is referred to as a molecular statement, which may be symbolized as p v q. The v symbol just used is a connective: Atomic propositions become molecular propositions when they are joined by connectives.
-
Originally, logic consisted only of [[deductive reasoning]] which concerns what follows universally from given premises.  However, it is important to note that [[inductive reasoning]]—the study of deriving a reliable generalization from observations—has sometimes been included in the study of logic. Correspondingly, we must distinguish between deductive validity and inductive validity.  An inference is deductively valid if and only if there is no possible situation in which all the premises are true and the conclusion false.  The notion of deductive validity can be rigorously stated for systems of [[formal logic]] in terms of the well-understood notions of [[semantics]].  Inductive validity on the other hand requires us to define a ''reliable generalization'' of some set of observations. The task of providing this definition may be approached  in various ways, some less formal than others; some of these definitions may use [[mathematical model]]s of probability.  For the most part this discussion of logic deals only with deductive logic.
+
===Predicate Logic===
-
==History of logic==
+
However, just as limits in Classical Logical led to [[Propositional Logic]], limits in Propositional Logic pointed to the need for a new logic. Propositional Logic is not adequate for formalizing valid arguments that rely on the internal structure of the propositions involved. For example, a translation of the valid argument:
-
{{main|History of logic}}
+
-
While many cultures have employed intricate systems of reasoning and math, logic as an explicit analysis of the methods of reasoning received sustained development originally only in three places: [[Indian logic|India]] in the [[6th century BC]], [[Logic in China|China]] in the [[5th century BC]], and [[Greek philosophy|Greece]] between the [[4th century BC]] and the [[1st century BC]].
+
    * All men are mortal
 +
    * Socrates is a man
 +
    * Therefore, Socrates is mortal
-
The formally sophisticated treatment of modern logic apparently descends from the Greek tradition, although it is suggested that the pioneers of [[Boolean logic]] were likely aware of Indian logic (Ganeri 2001). The Greek tradition itself comes mainly from the transmission of [[Aristotelian logic]], which probably developed independently of [[Indian logic]],  and commentary upon it by [[Islamic philosophy|Islamic philosophers]] to [[Medieval logic]]ians.  The traditions outside Europe did not survive into the modern era: in China, the tradition of scholarly investigation into logic was repressed by the [[Qin dynasty]] following the legalist philosophy of [[Han Feizi]], in the Islamic world the rise of the [[Asharite]] school suppressed original work on logic.
+
into propositional logic yields
-
However in India, innovations in the scholastic school, called [[Nyaya]], continued into the early [[18th century]]. It did not survive long into the [[Colonial India|colonial period]]. In the 20th century, western philosophers like [[Stanislaw Schayer]] and [[Klaus Glashoff]] have tried to explore certain aspects of the [[Indian logic|Indian tradition of logic]].
+
    * A
 +
    * B
 +
    * ∴ C (∴ means "therefore"
-
During the medieval period, after it was shown that Aristotle's ideas were largely compatible with faith, a greater emphasis was placed upon Aristotle's logic. During the later period of the medieval ages, logic became a main focus of philosophers, who would engage in critical logical analyses of philosophical arguments.
+
which is invalid, because there are no connectors between the premises and between the premises and the conclusion.
-
==Topics in logic==
+
Therefore, the need for a ''First Order'', or [[Predicate Logic]] became apparent. The new ingredient of first-order logic not found in propositional logic is [[Predicate Logic|quantification]]: where φ is any (well-formed) formula, the new constructions ∀x φ and ∃x φ — read "for all x, φ" and "for some x, φ" — are introduced, where x is an individual variable whose range is the set of individuals of some given universe of discourse (or domain). For example, if the universe consists solely of people, then x ranges over people. For convenience, we write φ as φ(x) to show that it contains only the variable x free and, for b a member of the universe, we let φ[b] express that b satisfies (i.e. has the property expressed by) φ. Then ∀x φ(x) states that φ[b] is true for every b in the universe, and ∃x φ(x) means that there is a b (in the universe) such that φ[b] holds.
-
Throughout history, there has been interest in distinguishing good from bad arguments, and so logic has been studied in some more or less familiar form.
+
The argument about Socrates can be formalized in first-order logic as follows. Let the universe of discourse be the set of all people, living and deceased, and let Man(x) be a predicate (which, informally, means that the person represented by variable x is a man) and Mortal(x) be a second predicate. Then the argument above becomes
-
[[Aristotelian logic]] has principally been concerned with teaching good argument, and is still taught with that end today, while in [[mathematical logic]] and [[analytical philosophy]] much greater emphasis is placed on logic as an object of study in its own right, and so logic is studied at a more abstract level.
+
-
Consideration of the different types of logic explains that logic is not studied in a vacuum. While logic often seems to provide its own motivations, the subject develops most healthily when the reason for our interest is made clear.
+
    * ∀ x (Man(x) → Mortal(x))
 +
    * Man(Socrates)
 +
    * ∴ Mortal(Socrates)
-
===Syllogistic logic===
+
A literal translation of the first line would be "For all x, if x is described by 'Man', x must also be described by 'Mortal'." The second line states that the predicate "Man" applies to Socrates, and the third line translates to "Therefore, the description 'Mortal' applies to Socrates."
-
{{main|Aristotelian logic}}
+
-
The ''[[Organon]]'' was [[Aristotle]]'s body of work on logic, with the ''[[Prior Analytics]]'' constituting the first explicit work in [[formal logic]], introducing the [[syllogistic]].  The parts of [[syllogistic]], also known by the name [[term logic]], were the analysis of the judgements into propositions consisting of two terms that are related by one of a fixed number of relations, and the expression of inferences by means of [[syllogism]]s that consisted of two propositions sharing a common term as premise, and a conclusion which was a proposition involving the two unrelated terms from the premises.
 
-
 
-
Aristotle's work was regarded in classical times and from medieval times in Europe and the Middle East as the very picture of a fully worked out system.  It was not alone: the [[Stoics]] proposed a system of [[propositional logic]] that was studied by medieval logicians; nor was the perfection of Aristotle's system undisputed; for example the [[problem of multiple generality]] was recognised in medieval times.  Nonetheless, problems with syllogistic logic were not seen as being in need of revolutionary solutions.
 
-
 
-
Today, some academics claim that Aristotle's system is generally seen as having little more than historical value (though there is some current interest in extending term logics), regarded as made obsolete by the advent of [[sentential logic]] and the [[predicate calculus]].  Others use Aristotle in [[argumentation theory]] to help develop and critically question argumentation schemes that are used in [[artificial intelligence]] and [[legal]] arguments.
 
-
 
-
===Predicate logic===
 
-
{{main|Predicate logic}}
 
-
 
-
Logic as it is studied today is a very different subject to that studied before, and the principal difference is the innovation of predicate logic.  Whereas Aristotelian syllogistic logic specified the forms that the relevant parts of the involved judgements took, predicate logic allows sentences to be analysed into subject and argument in several different ways, thus allowing predicate logic to solve the [[problem of multiple generality]] that had perplexed medieval logicians.  With predicate logic, for the first time, logicians were able to give an account of [[quantifiers]] general enough to express all arguments occurring in natural language.
 
-
 
-
The discovery of predicate logic is usually attributed to [[Gottlob Frege]], who is also credited as one of the founders of [[analytical philosophy]], but the formulation of predicate logic most often used today is the [[first-order logic]] presented in [[Principles of Theoretical Logic]] by [[David Hilbert]] and [[Wilhelm Ackermann]] in [[1928]].  The analytical generality of the predicate logic allowed the formalisation of mathematics, and drove the investigation of [[set theory]], allowed the development of [[Alfred Tarski]]'s approach to [[model theory]]; it is no exaggeration to say that it is the foundation of modern [[mathematical logic]].
 
-
 
-
Frege's original system of predicate logic was not first-, but second-order. [[Second-order logic]] is most prominently defended (against the criticism of [[Willard Van Orman Quine]] and others) by [[George Boolos]] and [[Stewart Shapiro]].
 
===Modal logic===
===Modal logic===
-
{{main|Modal logic}}
 
In language, [[modality]] deals with the phenomenon that subparts of a sentence may have their semantics modified by special verbs or modal particles.  For example, "''We go to the games''" can be modified to give "''We should go to the games''", and "''We can go to the games''"" and perhaps "''We will go to the games''".  More abstractly, we might say that modality affects the circumstances in which we take an assertion to be satisfied.
In language, [[modality]] deals with the phenomenon that subparts of a sentence may have their semantics modified by special verbs or modal particles.  For example, "''We go to the games''" can be modified to give "''We should go to the games''", and "''We can go to the games''"" and perhaps "''We will go to the games''".  More abstractly, we might say that modality affects the circumstances in which we take an assertion to be satisfied.
-
The logical study of modality dates back to [[Aristotle]], who was concerned with the [[alethic modalities]] of necessity and possibility, which he observed to be dual in the sense of [[De Morgan duality]].  While the study of necessity and possibility remained important to philosophers, little logical innovation happened until the landmark investigations of [[Clarence Irving Lewis]] in [[1918]], who formulated a family of rival axiomatisations of the alethic modalities.  His work unleashed a torrent of new work on the topic, expanding the kinds of modality treated to include [[deontic logic]] and [[epistemic logic]].  The seminal work of [[Arthur Prior]] applied the same formal language to treat [[temporal logic]] and paved the way for the marriage of the two subjects.  [[Saul Kripke]] discovered (contemporaneously with rivals) his theory of [[frame semantics]] which revolutionised the formal technology available to modal logicians and gave a new [[graph theory|graph-theoretic]] way of looking at modality that has driven many applications in [[computational linguistics]] and [[computer science]], such as [[dynamic logic]].
+
The logical study of modality dates back to [[Aristotle]], who was concerned with the [[alethic modalities]] of necessity and possibility, which he observed to be dual in the sense of [[De Morgan duality]].  While the study of necessity and possibility remained important to philosophers, little logical innovation happened until the landmark investigations of [[Clarence Irving Lewis]] in [[1918]], who formulated a family of rival axiomatisations of the alethic modalities.  His work unleashed a torrent of new work on the topic, expanding the kinds of modality treated to include [[deontic logic]] and [[epistemic logic]].  The seminal work of [[Arthur Prior]] applied the same formal language to treat [[temporal logic]] and paved the way for the marriage of the two subjects.  [[Saul Kripke]] discovered (contemporaneously with rivals) his theory of [[frame semantics]] which revolutionized the formal technology available to modal logicians and gave a new [[graph theory|graph-theoretic]] way of looking at modality that has driven many applications in [[computational linguistics]] and [[computer science]], such as [[dynamic logic]].
-
===Deduction and reasoning===
 
-
{{main|Deductive reasoning}}
 
-
The motivation for the study of logic in ancient times was clear, as we have described: it is so that we may learn to distinguish good from bad arguments, and so become more effective in argument and oratory, and perhaps also, to become a better person.
+
----
-
 
+
Students following the [[Course in Logic 101]] should proceed to the section entitled: [[The Laws of Classical Logic]]
-
This motivation is still alive, although it no longer takes centre stage in the picture of logic; typically dialectical logic will form the heart of a course in [[critical thinking]], a compulsory course at many universities, especially those that follow the American model.
+
-
 
+
-
===Mathematical logic===
+
-
{{main|Mathematical logic}}
+
-
 
+
-
Mathematical logic really refers to two distinct areas of research: the first is the application of the techniques of formal logic to mathematics and mathematical reasoning, and the second, in the other direction, the application of mathematical techniques to the representation and analysis of formal logic.
+
-
 
+
-
The earliest use of math and [[geometry]] in relation to logic and philosophy goes back to the ancient Greeks such as [[Euclid]], [[Plato]], and [[Aristotle]].  Many other ancient and medieval philosophers applied mathematical ideas and methods to their philosophical claims.
+
-
 
+
-
The boldest attempt to apply logic to mathematics was undoubtedly the [[logicism]] pioneered by philosopher-logicians such as [[Gottlob Frege]] and [[Bertrand Russell]]: the idea was that mathematical theories were logical tautologies, and the programme was to show this by means to a reduction of mathematics to logic.  The various attempts to carry this out met with a series of failures, from the crippling of Frege's project in his ''Grundgesetze'' by [[Russell's paradox]], to the defeat of [[Hilbert's Program]] by [[Gödel's incompleteness theorem]]s.
+
-
 
+
-
Both the statement of Hilbert's Program and its refutation by Gödel depended upon their work establishing the second area of mathematical logic, the application of mathematics to logic in the form of [[proof theory]].  Despite the negative nature of the incompleteness theorems, [[Gödel's completeness theorem]], a result in [[model theory]] and another application of mathematics to logic, can be understood as showing how close logicism came to being true: every rigorously defined mathematical theory can be exactly captured by a first-order logical theory; Frege's [[proof calculus]] is enough to ''describe'' the whole of mathematics, though not ''equivalent'' to it.  Thus we see how complementary the two areas of mathematical logic have been.
+
-
 
+
-
If proof theory and model theory have been the foundation of mathematical logic, they have been but two of the four pillars of the subject.  [[Set theory]] originated in the study of the infinite by [[Georg Cantor]], and it has been the source of many of the most challenging and important issues in mathematical logic, from [[Cantor's theorem]], through the status of the [[Axiom of Choice]] and the question of the independence of the [[continuum hypothesis]], to the modern debate on [[large cardinal]] axioms.
+
-
 
+
-
[[Recursion theory]] captures the idea of computation in logical and [[arithmetic]] terms; its most classical achievements are the undecidability of the [[Entscheidungsproblem]] by [[Alan Turing]], and his presentation of the [[Church-Turing thesis]].  Today recursion theory is mostly concerned with the more refined problem of [[complexity class]]es -- when is a problem efficiently solvable? -- and the classification of [[Turing degree|degrees of unsolvability]].
+
-
 
+
-
===Philosophical logic===
+
-
{{main|Philosophical logic}}
+
-
 
+
-
[[Philosophical logic]] deals with formal descriptions of natural language.  Most philosophers assume that the bulk of "normal" proper reasoning can be captured by logic, if one can find the right method for translating ordinary language into that logic. Philosophical logic is essentially a continuation of the traditional discipline that was called "Logic" before it was supplanted by the invention of mathematical logic. Philosophical logic has a much greater concern with the connection between natural language and logic. As a result, philosophical logicians have contributed a great deal to the development of non-standard logics (e.g., [[free logic]]s, [[tense logic]]s) as well as various extensions of [[classical logic]] (e.g., [[modal logic]]s), and non-standard semantics for such logics (e.g., [[Kripke]]'s technique of supervaluations in the semantics of logic).
+
-
 
+
-
Logic and the philosophy of language are closely related.  Philosophy of language has to do with the study of how our language engages and interacts with our thinking.  Logic has an immediate impact on other areas of study.  Studying logic and the relationship between logic and ordinary speech can help a person better structure their own arguments and critique the arguments of others.  Many popular arguments are filled with errors because so many people are untrained in logic and unaware of how to correctly formulate an argument.
+
-
 
+
-
Philosophy of language underwent a renaissance in the 20th century because of the work of [[Ludwig  Wittgenstein]].
+
-
 
+
-
===Logic and computation===
+
-
{{main|Logic in computer science}}
+
-
 
+
-
Logic cut to the heart of computer science as it emerged as a discipline: [[Alan Turing]]'s work on the [[Entscheidungsproblem]] followed from [[Kurt Gödel]]'s work on the [[incompleteness theorems]], and the notion of general purpose computers that came from this work was of fundamental importance to the designers of the computer machinery in the [[1940s]]. 
+
-
 
+
-
In the 1950s and 1960s, researchers predicted that when human knowledge could be expressed using logic with [[mathematical notation]], it would be possible to create a machine that reasons, or artificial intelligence.  This turned out to be more difficult than expected because of the complexity of human reasoning.  In [[logic programming]], a program consists of a set of axioms and rules. Logic programming systems such as [[Prolog]] compute the consequences of the axioms and rules in order to answer a query.
+
-
 
+
-
Today, logic is extensively applied in the fields of [[artificial intelligence]], and [[computer science]], and these fields provide a rich source of problems in formal and informal logic.  [[Argumentation theory]] is one good example of how logic is being applied to artifical intelligence.  The [[ACM Computing Classification System]] in particular regards:
+
-
* Section F.3 on [[Logics and meanings of programs]] and F. 4 on [[Mathematical logic and formal languages]] as part of the theory of computer science: this work covers [[formal semantics of programming languages]], as well as work of [[formal methods]] such as [[Hoare logic]]
+
-
* [[Boolean logic]] as fundamental to computer hardware: particularly, the system's section B.2 on [[Arithmetic and logic structures]];
+
-
* Many fundamental logical formalisms are essential to section I.2 on artificial intelligence, for example [[modal logic]] and [[default logic]] in [[Knowledge representation formalisms and methods]], [[Horn clause]]s in [[logic programming]], and [[description logic]].
+
-
 
+
-
Furthermore, computers can be used as tools for logicians.  For example, in symbolic logic and mathematical logic, proofs by humans can be computer-assisted.  Using [[automated theorem proving]] the machines can find and check proofs, as well as work with proofs too lengthy to be written out by hand.
+
-
 
+
-
===Argumentation Theory===
+
-
 
+
-
[[Argumentation]] theory is the study and research of informal logic, fallacies, and critical questions as they relate to every day and practical situations.  Specific types of dialogue can be analyzed and questioned to reveal premises, conclusions, and fallacies.  Argumentation theory is now applied in [[artificial intelligence]] and [[law]].
+
-
 
+
-
==Controversies in logic==
+
-
 
+
-
Just as we have seen there is disagreement over what logic is about, so there is disagreement about what logical truths there are.
+
-
 
+
-
===Bivalence and the law of the excluded middle===
+
-
{{main|Classical logic}}
+
-
 
+
-
The logics discussed above are all "[[Bivalent (logic)|bivalent]]" or "two-valued"; that is, they are most naturally understood as dividing propositions into the true and the false propositions.  Systems which reject bivalence are known as [[non-classical logic]]s.
+
-
 
+
-
In 1910 [[Nicolai A. Vasiliev]] rejected the law of excluded middle and the law of contradiction and proposed the law of excluded fourth and logic tolerant to contradiction. In the early [[20th century]] [[Jan Łukasiewicz]] investigated the extension of the traditional true/false values to include a third value, "possible", so inventing [[ternary logic]], the first [[multi-valued logic]].
+
-
 
+
-
[[Intuitionistic logic]] was proposed by [[L.E.J. Brouwer]] as the correct logic for reasoning about mathematics, based upon his rejection of the [[law of the excluded middle]] as part of his [[intuitionism]].  Brouwer rejected formalisation in mathematics, but his student [[Arend Heyting]] studied intuitionistic logic formally, as did [[Gerhard Gentzen]].  Intuitionistic logic has come to be of great interest to computer scientists, as it is a [[constructive logic]], and is hence a logic of what computers can do.
+
-
 
+
-
[[Modal logic]] is not truth conditional, and so it has often been proposed as a non-classical logic.  However, modal logic is normally formalised with the principle of the excluded middle, and its [[relational semantics]] is bivalent, so this inclusion is disputable.  On the other hand, modal logic can be used to encode non-classical logics, such as intuitionistic logic.
+
-
 
+
-
Logics such as [[fuzzy logic]] have since been devised with an infinite number of "degrees of truth", represented by a [[real number]] between 0 and 1.  [[Bayesian probability]] can be interpreted as a system of logic where probability is the subjective truth value.
+
-
 
+
-
===Implication: strict or material?===
+
-
{{main|Paradox of entailment}}
+
-
 
+
-
It is obvious that the notion of implication formalised in classical logic does not comfortably translate into natural language by means of "if... then...", due to a number of
+
-
problems called the ''paradoxes of material implication''.
+
-
 
+
-
The first class of paradoxes involves counterfactuals, such as "If the moon is made of green cheese, then 2+2=5", which are puzzling because natural language does not support the [[principle of explosion]].  Eliminating this class of paradoxes was the reason for [[C. I. Lewis]]'s formulation of [[strict implication]], which eventually led to more radically revisionist logics such as [[relevance logic]].
+
-
 
+
-
The second class of paradoxes involves redundant premises, falsely suggesting that we know the succedent because of the antecedent: thus "if that man gets elected, granny will die" is materially true if granny happens to be in the last stages of a terminal illness, regardless of the man's election prospects.  Such sentences violate the [[Gricean maxim]] of relevance, and can be modelled by logics that reject the principle of [[monotonicity of entailment]], such as relevance logic.
+
-
 
+
-
===Tolerating the impossible===
+
-
{{main|Paraconsistent logic}}
+
-
 
+
-
Closely related to questions arising from the paradoxes of implication comes the radical suggestion that logic ought to tolerate [[inconsistency]].  [[Relevance logic]] and [[paraconsistent logic]] are the most important approaches here, though the concerns are different: a key consequence of [[classical logic]] and some of its rivals, such as [[intuitionistic logic]], is that they respect the [[principle of explosion]], which means that the logic collapses if it is capable of deriving a contradiction.  [[Graham Priest]], the main proponent of dialetheism, has argued for paraconsistency on the striking grounds that there are in fact, true contradictions (Priest 2004).
+
-
 
+
-
===Is logic empirical?===
+
-
{{main|Is logic empirical?}}
+
-
     
+
-
What is the epistemological status of the [[laws of logic]]?  What sort of arguments is appropriate for criticising purported principles of logic?  In an influential paper entitled ''Is logic empirical?'' [[Hilary Putnam]], building on a suggestion of [[W.V. Quine]], argued that in general the facts of propositional logic have a similar epistemological status as facts about the physical universe, for example as the laws of [[mechanics]] or of [[general relativity]], and in particular that what physicists have learned about quantum mechanics provides a compelling case for abandoning certain familiar principles of classical logic: if we want to be [[philosophical realism|realists]] about the physical phenomena described by quantum theory, then we should abandon the [[principle of distributivity]], substituting for classical logic the [[quantum logic]] proposed by [[Garrett Birkhoff]] and [[John von Neumann]].
+
-
 
+
-
Another paper by the same name by [[Sir Michael Dummett]] argues that Putnam's desire for realism mandates the law of distributivity: distributivity of logic is essential for the realist's understanding of how propositions are true of the world, in just the same way as he has argued the principle of bivalence is.  In this way, the question ''Is logic empirical?'' can be seen to lead naturally into the fundamental controversy in [[metaphysics]] on [[realism versus anti-realism]].
+
==References==
==References==
Line 220: Line 135:
* [[Graham Priest|Priest, Graham]] (2004), "Dialetheism", ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', Edward N. Zalta (ed.), [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/dialetheism Eprint].
* [[Graham Priest|Priest, Graham]] (2004), "Dialetheism", ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', Edward N. Zalta (ed.), [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/dialetheism Eprint].
-
 
+
-
* [[Hilary Putnam|Putnam, H.]] (1969), "Is Logic Empirical?", ''Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science' 5.
+
-
 
+
* [[Barry Smith|Smith, B.]] (1989), "Logic and the Sachverhalt", ''The Monist'' 72(1), 52–69.
* [[Barry Smith|Smith, B.]] (1989), "Logic and the Sachverhalt", ''The Monist'' 72(1), 52–69.
-
==See also==
+
==See also==  
-
{{col-begin}}
+
* [[Course in Logic 101]] This takes the interested reader to every major page of the site.
-
{{col-break}}
+
* [[The Laws of Classical Logic]] This page presents the axioms of classical logic
-
* [[Logical consequence]]
+
* [[Validity, Strength, Soundness and Cogency ]]
-
* [[Logic puzzle]]
+
* [[Deductive and Inductive Logic]]
-
* [[Probabilistic logic]]
+
* [[Fallacies|Logical Fallacies]]
-
{{col-break}}
+
* [[Informal Fallacies]] This page presents a list of informal fallacies found in arguments.
-
* [[Propositional logic]]
+
* [[Formal Fallacies]]
-
* [[Truth]]
+
* [[Valid and Invalid Logical Forms]]
-
* [[Truth theory]]
+
* [[Categorical Propositions]]
-
{{col-end}}
+
* [[Classical Logic]]
-
 
+
* [[Propositional Logic]]  
-
 
+
* [[Predicate Logic]]
-
==External links==
+
* [[Inductive Logic]]
-
{{Sisterlinks|Logic}}
+
-
 
+
-
* {{wikia|logic|LogicWiki}}
+
-
* {{memoryalpha}}
+
-
* ''[http://www.galilean-library.org/int4.html An Introduction to Philosophical Logic]'', by Paul Newall, aimed at beginners
+
-
* ''[http://www.fecundity.com/logic/ forall x: an introduction to formal logic]'', by P.D. Magnus, covers sentential and quantified logic
+
-
* ''[http://www.earlham.edu/~peters/courses/log/transtip.htm Translation Tips]'', by Peter Suber, for translating from English into logical notation
+
-
* [http://etext.lib.virginia.edu/DicHist/analytic/anaVII.html Math & Logic: The history of formal mathematical, logical, linguistic and methodological ideas.] In ''The Dictionary of the History of Ideas.''
+
-
{{Philosophy (navigation)}}
 
-
{{EnWP|Logic}}
 
-
[[Category:Logic| ]]
+
[[Category:Logic]]
-
[[Category:Branches of philosophy]]
+
[[Category:Tutorials]]

Revision as of 20:32, 18 June 2007

Contents

Introduction

This site is intended as a resource for those interested in learning Logic. While the author of this page will take a scholarly approach to the subject, this page will approach the subject in a more user friendly manner than available at Wikipedia, at times even using colloquial language. The site will offer a full Course in Logic 101, based on two of the most reliable texts on logic: Copi and Cohen's Introduction to Logic (11th Edition) and Hurely's A Concise Introduction to Logic (7th Edition). The course will cover the basics of Logic, Classical Logic, Propositional Logic, Predicate Logic, Modal Logic and Inductive Logic including a discussion of Bayesian Theory. Those interested in taking the course can consult that page for the proper order of reading the pages of this site.

Now, let's begin.

Logic, (from the Greek word λόγος (logos), originally meaning the word, but also referring to speech or reason) is the science of evaluating the reasoning within arguments.

Nature of logic

Logic arose from a concern with correctness of argumentation (See Aristotle). Logic is generally accepted and understood by logicians as a set of rules that tell us when an argument's premises support their conclusion. Logic specifically deals with inferences whose validity can be traced back to the formal features of the representations that are involved in that inference. (Hofweber 2004).

Therefore, a further understanding of just what logic is, can be enhanced by delineating it from what it is not:

  • Logic is not the 'groundness of being' - that's metaphysics.
  • Logic is not a set of laws that governs the universe - that's physics.
  • Logic is not an immaterial "entity" that transcends reality - that's speculative theology.
  • Logic is no a method for 'studying the world' - that's science.
  • Logic is not the method for assessing axioms - that's a matter of pure reason.
  • Logic is not a way of evaluating 'truth' - that's philosophy.
  • Logic is not a set of laws that governs human behavior - that's psychology.
  • Logic is not even a study of how people reason - Fortunately there is more to human reason than just logic.

Immanuel Kant introduced an alternative idea as to what logic is. He argued that logic should be conceived as the science of judgment, an idea taken up by Gottlob Frege. However, modern psychologists have demonstrated that a significant percentage of human judgment is clearly non logical.


Relation to other sciences

Closely related to logic is semantics, or the philosophy of language, which concerns the meaning of the words and sentences; epistemology, or the theory of knowledge, which concerns the conditions under which assertions are true; and the psychology of reasoning, which concerns the mental processes involved in reasoning. Logic, however, is generally understood to describe reasoning in a prescriptive manner (i.e. it describes how reasoning ought to take place), whereas psychology is descriptive and therefore more inclusive vis-a-vis the various methods of judgment humans actually use.

Definition of an Argument

An argument is made up of a group of statements we call propositions. We use the term proposition instead of sentence because a proposition is more than just a sentence, it is a declarative sentence that contains a truth value. In the case of Classical Logic, which is based on the Law of the Excluded Middle, this truth value must either be "true" or false" .

There are two types of Propositions. The first, the Premise, makes a commitment to truth, and is used as evidence to support the second type of proposition, the Conclusion, which is the claim the arguer wants to prove. An argument must at least imply one of each. The study of logic, therefore, is the effort to determine the conditions under which one is justified in passing from the premises to the conclusion that logically must follow them.

Examining Arguments: Informal, formal, and symbolic logic

Arguments can be examined through examining their premises, the form of the argument, and by looking at them abstractly. We use the terms "informal", "formal" and "symbolic" to capture these meanings.

  • Informal Logic is the study of natural language arguments. The study of fallacies is an especially important branch of informal logic.
  • Formal Logic is the study of inference with purely formal content, where that content is made explicit. (An inference possesses a purely formal content if it can be expressed as a particular application of a wholly abstract rule, that is, a rule that is not about any particular thing or property. We will see later that on many definitions of logic, logical inference and inference with purely formal content are the same thing. This does not render the notion of informal logic vacuous, since one may wish to investigate logic without committing to a particular formal analysis.)
  • Symbolic Logic is closely related to formal logic: it the study of symbolic abstractions that capture the formal features of logical inference.

Consistency, soundness, and completeness

There are three valuable properties that formal systems can have:

  • Consistency, which means that none of the theorems of the system contradict each other.
  • Soundness, which means that the system's rules of derivation will never let you infer anything false, so long as you start with only true premises. So if a system is sound (and its axioms, if any, are true), then the theorems of a sound formal system are the truths. All of the theorems of a system that has no axioms are its truths and sometimes the truths of such a system are called 'logical truths.' (Note that if a system is not consistent, it cannot be sound. This is because a contradiction is always false, so if two theorems contradict at least one is false.)
  • Completeness, which means that there are no true sentences in the system that cannot, at least in principle, be proved using the derivation rules (and axioms, if any) of the system.

Not all systems achieve all three virtues. It has been proven by Kurt Gödel that a system with enough axioms and/or rules of derivation to derive the principles of arithmetic cannot be both consistent and complete. This is called Gödel's Incompleteness Theorem.

Deductive and inductive reasoning

Originally, logic consisted only of deductive reasoning which concerns what follows universally from given premises. However, it is important to note that inductive reasoning—the study of deriving a reliable generalization from observations—has sometimes been included in the study of logic. Correspondingly, we must distinguish between deductive validity and inductive validity. An inference is deductively valid if and only if there is no possible situation in which all the premises are true and the conclusion false. The notion of deductive validity can be rigorously stated for systems of formal logic in terms of the well-understood notions of semantics. Inductive validity on the other hand requires us to define a reliable generalization of some set of observations. The task of providing this definition may be approached in various ways, some less formal than others; some of these definitions may use mathematical models of probability. For the most part this discussion of logic deals only with deductive logic.

Types of logic

Formal logic encompasses a wide variety of logical systems. Various systems of logic include Classical or Syllogistic logic, Predicate Logic, Propositional Logic, and Modal Logic, and formal systems are indispensable in all branches of mathematical logic. The table of logic symbols describes various widely used notations in symbolic logic.

Syllogistic or Classical Logic

The Organon was Aristotle's body of work on logic, with the Prior Analytics constituting the first explicit work in formal logic, introducing to the world the syllogism. Syllogistic Logic, Term logic, Aristotelean Logic or Classical Logic are all references to the logical form of the syllogism. Syllogistic logic is the analysis of the judgments into propositions consisting of two terms that are related by one of a fixed number of relations, and the expression of inferences by means of syllogisms that consisted of two propositions sharing a common term as premise, and a conclusion which was a proposition involving the two unrelated terms from the premises.

Aristotle's work was regarded in classical times and from medieval times in Europe and the Middle East as the very picture of a fully worked out system. It was not alone: the Stoics proposed a system of Propositional Logic that was studied by medieval logicians; nor was the perfection of Aristotle's system undisputed; for example the problem of multiple generality was recognized in medieval times. Nonetheless, problems with syllogistic logic were not seen as being in need of revolutionary solutions.

Today, some academics claim that Aristotle's system is generally seen as having little more than historical value (though there is some current interest in extending term logics), regarded as made obsolete by the advent of Sentential Logic and the predicate calculus.

Propositional Logic

Logic as it is studied today is a very different subject from Classical Logic; the principal difference is the innovation of Propositional Logic and Predicate Logic. Propositional Logic allows for more complex argument forms than classical syllogisms. In propositional logic, propositions are represented by symbols and connectors, so that the statement's logical form can be assessed for cases of truth and falsity, which in turn allows us to assess the entire argument's form for validity or invalidity. In symbolic, or propositional logic, a simple statement, containing one proposition, is is referred to as an atomic statement, and is symbolized by one letter, such as p. A compound statement, with more than one proposition holding some relationship to another proposition, is referred to as a molecular statement, which may be symbolized as p v q. The v symbol just used is a connective: Atomic propositions become molecular propositions when they are joined by connectives.

Predicate Logic

However, just as limits in Classical Logical led to Propositional Logic, limits in Propositional Logic pointed to the need for a new logic. Propositional Logic is not adequate for formalizing valid arguments that rely on the internal structure of the propositions involved. For example, a translation of the valid argument:

   * All men are mortal
   * Socrates is a man
   * Therefore, Socrates is mortal

into propositional logic yields

   * A
   * B
   * ∴ C (∴ means "therefore"

which is invalid, because there are no connectors between the premises and between the premises and the conclusion.

Therefore, the need for a First Order, or Predicate Logic became apparent. The new ingredient of first-order logic not found in propositional logic is quantification: where φ is any (well-formed) formula, the new constructions ∀x φ and ∃x φ — read "for all x, φ" and "for some x, φ" — are introduced, where x is an individual variable whose range is the set of individuals of some given universe of discourse (or domain). For example, if the universe consists solely of people, then x ranges over people. For convenience, we write φ as φ(x) to show that it contains only the variable x free and, for b a member of the universe, we let φ[b] express that b satisfies (i.e. has the property expressed by) φ. Then ∀x φ(x) states that φ[b] is true for every b in the universe, and ∃x φ(x) means that there is a b (in the universe) such that φ[b] holds.

The argument about Socrates can be formalized in first-order logic as follows. Let the universe of discourse be the set of all people, living and deceased, and let Man(x) be a predicate (which, informally, means that the person represented by variable x is a man) and Mortal(x) be a second predicate. Then the argument above becomes

   * ∀ x (Man(x) → Mortal(x))
   * Man(Socrates)
   * ∴ Mortal(Socrates)

A literal translation of the first line would be "For all x, if x is described by 'Man', x must also be described by 'Mortal'." The second line states that the predicate "Man" applies to Socrates, and the third line translates to "Therefore, the description 'Mortal' applies to Socrates."


Modal logic

In language, modality deals with the phenomenon that subparts of a sentence may have their semantics modified by special verbs or modal particles. For example, "We go to the games" can be modified to give "We should go to the games", and "We can go to the games"" and perhaps "We will go to the games". More abstractly, we might say that modality affects the circumstances in which we take an assertion to be satisfied.

The logical study of modality dates back to Aristotle, who was concerned with the alethic modalities of necessity and possibility, which he observed to be dual in the sense of De Morgan duality. While the study of necessity and possibility remained important to philosophers, little logical innovation happened until the landmark investigations of Clarence Irving Lewis in 1918, who formulated a family of rival axiomatisations of the alethic modalities. His work unleashed a torrent of new work on the topic, expanding the kinds of modality treated to include deontic logic and epistemic logic. The seminal work of Arthur Prior applied the same formal language to treat temporal logic and paved the way for the marriage of the two subjects. Saul Kripke discovered (contemporaneously with rivals) his theory of frame semantics which revolutionized the formal technology available to modal logicians and gave a new graph-theoretic way of looking at modality that has driven many applications in computational linguistics and computer science, such as dynamic logic.



Students following the Course in Logic 101 should proceed to the section entitled: The Laws of Classical Logic

References

  • Birkhoff, G., and von Neumann, J. (1936), "The Logic of Quantum Mechanics", Annals of Mathematics 37, 823–843.
  • Cohen, R.S, and Wartofsky, M.W. (1974), Logical and Epistemological Studies in Contemporary Physics, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Netherlands. ISBN 90-277-0377-9.
  • Finkelstein, D. (1969), "Matter, Space, and Logic", in R.S. Cohen and M.W. Wartofsky (eds. 1974).
  • Gabbay, D.M., and Guenthner, F. (eds., 2001-2005), Handbook of Philosophical Logic, 13 vols., 2nd edition, Kluwer Publishers, Dordrecht.
  • Hodges, W. (2001), Logic. An introduction to Elementary Logic, Penguin Books.
  • Hughes, R.I.G. (ed., 1993), A Philosophical Companion to First-Order Logic, Hackett Publishing.
  • Priest, Graham (2004), "Dialetheism", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Edward N. Zalta (ed.), Eprint.
  • Smith, B. (1989), "Logic and the Sachverhalt", The Monist 72(1), 52–69.

See also

Personal tools